TRANSLATE THIS ARTICLE
Integral World: Exploring Theories of Everything
An independent forum for a critical discussion of the integral philosophy of Ken Wilber
SEE MORE ESSAYS WRITTEN BY ANDY SMITH
A ONE-SCALE MODEL
OF HOLARCHY
And it's implications for four strand theories of knowledge acquisition.
A response to Mark Edwards
I have recently read your magnificent paper, 'The Integral Cycle of
Knowledge: Some thoughts on Integrating Ken Wilber's Developmental and
Epistemological Models", which I discovered on The World of Ken Wilber
website. I feel you show great perception concerning both what Wilber has
actually said and what he appears to mean, and your main theme, the need for
an additional strand in the knowledge acquisition process, is not simply
well argued, but suggests a unification with Wilber's developmental model.
Any approach that can do that has to be taken very seriously. Several other
correlations revealed by your arguments, such as that between the strands of
knowledge and the structure of a typical scientific paper, I thought were
brilliant. And last but not least, you show great fairness and respect for
Wilber and his ideas throughout this long paper, not a little matter to
judge from the tone taken by at least a few of his other critics. All in
all, I feel this paper is a model for the kind of dialogue needed in
discussions of a new paradigm. I would like to join this discussion by offering some more detailed
comments on your paper. Though some of them are critical, I will say at the
outset that I am in fairly broad agreement with your argument. Furthermore,
the most important contribution I feel I have to make is not a criticism of
your ideas, but an extension of them. In much the same way that you have
attempted to strengthen Wilber's project, I am offering what I believe is an
approach that will strengthen yours.
A One-scale Model of Holarchy
The heart of this approach is my contention that Wilber's
four-quadrant
model of holarchical existence, which plays such a central role in your
argument, is unnecessarily differentiated. I have recently presented a
detailed model of holarchy which requires but a single axis or scale, thus
unifying both the individual vs. social and the interior vs. exterior
dimensions of Wilber's model. This one-scale model is presented in an
article, "A One-scale Model of Holarchical Existence", and in much more
detail, in a book, Worlds within Worlds. The Holarchical View of Existence.
Links to both of these documents have been posted on my own website
(www.geocities.com/andybalik/introduction.html), and I refer you to them for
more details concerning most of the points that follow.
Briefly, and incompletely, the argument goes as follows. Wilber's
need for
a social dimension, it seems to me, is based on a confusion or conflation of
two kinds of "societies". One kind, exemplified by galaxies that are
composed of atoms, and the Gaia system that is composed of prokaryotic
cells, lacks much organization. These "societies" are essentially just
undifferentiated aggregates of large numbers of individual holons. They
have few if any truly emergent properties. For this reason, Wilber
considers them to be on the same level of existence as their individual
members, and I agree with him on this point. The other kind of society,
however, that composed of humans, is very different. Human societies are
highly organized, and very definitely do have emergent properties. They
are, in my model, analogous to the higher biological stages (tissues,
organs, etc.), having much the same relationship to their individual members
as the higher biological stages have to their individual cells (I want to
emphasize that I am not saying that human societies are "like organisms". I
am saying they are analogous to certain kinds of holons found within
organisms. If even this analogy seems imperfect in some respects, it must
be kept in mind that whereas the higher biological stages have finished
evolving, human societies have not. This point is discussed at some length
in my book). Therefore, just as these higher biological stages can be (and
are) placed above individual cells on a single scale or axis in Wilber's
model, so, I argue, should human societies be placed above individual humans
in this model.
This results in the elimination of most of the social dimension in
his
holarchy, that is, the distinction between it and the individual dimension.
While there is still a valid distinction to be made between what I call
social holons (e.g., human societies, biological tissues) and fundamental
holons (e.g., cells, organisms), they can both be placed on a single scale,
with the social holons (at any particular level) above the individual
holons. Thus human societies are above individual humans; biological
tissues and organs are above cells; large and small molecules are above
atoms. The loose societies like galaxies and Gaia don't take this position,
because as Wilber and I agree, they are not really higher than their
individual members; but for just this reason, I don't feel it necessary to
give them a special position or axis in the holarchy. We can understand
that groups of atoms or groups of prokaryotes are all in one holarchical
position, regardless of how many individuals are in the groups.
The argument for bringing together the exterior and interior
dimensions of
Wilber's model is a little more complicated, and again, I refer you to the
article of the book (in the latter, this discussion appears in the last part
of Chapter 4). However, there is a very quick way of making this point.
All of us, Wilber included, agree that the holarchy can be described in very
abbreviated terms as something like "matter, life, mind, spirit", with other
levels likely or possible below and above these four. Since mind is
certainly an interior property in Wilber's sense, and since the brain, as a
biological organization of nerve cells, is an exterior property, it follows
that mind is above the brain--not on the same level in a different quadrant
or dimension as Wilber places it. Just where in the holarchy it is, and its
relationship to brain on a single scale, is a question I will return to in a
moment.
First, though, I do need to emphasize that in order to eliminate
Wilber's
interior dimension (or speaking more precisely, unify it with the exterior
one), I assume that Wilber really means two things by the term
interior--that is, it includes phenomena that a large number of scientists,
psychologists and philosophers divide into two classes. These two classes
are functional properties of mind--learning, memory, cognition, etc.--and
what I call experiential properties. Functional properties are those that
have some outward manifestation that another observer can measure;
experiential properties are philosophers' qualia, the experience of
consciousness itself. These two classes correspond to what philosopher
David Chalmers (1996) calls, respectively, the "soft" and "hard" problems of
consciousness. Most scientists and philosophers believe the soft properties
can be explained completely in terms of the interactions of cells in the
nervous system (even if we haven't succeeded in this project yet)--which is
to say, exterior properties. Some theorists, however, including Chalmers,
are not so sure we will ever be able to explain the hard problem in this
way.
From the way Wilber has described interior properties (in, for
example,
Sex, Ecology, Spirituality, 1995), I'm quite sure he means both of these
classes of mind. My arguments against a separate interior scale, however,
are directed only against the soft or functional properties. I think it
would be very difficult to conceive of a scale in which mind or
consciousness in the hard sense bears the same relationship to, say,
biological tissues and cells, as they do to still lower forms of
organization. I consider consciousness in this sense as something outside
or beyond the holarchy. Every form of existence has some degree of
consciousness, by virtue of its position within the holarchy, and this
degree manifests itself in certain functional properties. But there is in
my model an irreducible concsciousness that is not dealt with on the scale.
This consciousness is unitary in the sense that it pervades all of
existence. For this reason, I don't feel that it can be placed on any scale
which implies levels or degrees.
Nevertheless, what I call the functional or soft aspects of
consciousness
include a great deal of mental phenomena, including what some people might
loosely refer to as experience. For example, in your article (p. 20 in my
printed version, which runs to a total of 30 pages, including references)
you state that "it is also the case that interiors can be included in the
intepretation of purely objective data/behavior through inference and the
inclusion of subjectivity as a basic element in the interpretative framework
for the data." Chalmers would argue, and I agree, that all of this interior
knowledge, obtained through the advances of cognitive and then evolutionary
psychology that you subsequently discuss, is part of the soft aspects of
consciousness. Even the dialogical discussion that I am having with you
right now involves soft, not hard, aspects of consciousness. Though you
define dialogical science as "that type of science that emphasizes the
experiential and interpretive strands" (p. 23), one can imagine a zombie--a
being with a functional mentality identical to an ordinary human being, yet
with no conscious experience (Chalmers 1996)--capable of having the
identical discussion. So dialogical science and interpretation are not
(necessarily) experiential in the sense I am defining it, and little wonder
that it can sometimes employ the same kinds of methods used successfully to
obtain knowledge about exteriors (a critical point in your paper that I will
return to).
Having made this distinction in interior properties, let's return to
the
question of where in the holarchy the soft or functional aspects of mind or
consciousness are. Much of your article, and the best argued part in my
opinion, is devoted to trying to convince the reader that different levels
of the holarchy can be approached by both monological and dialogical
methods. Much of this argument is summarized in Table 3, and in subsequent
tables. While I have some differences with you over some of the examples
shown in these tables (see below), there are broad areas of agreement, and
particularly with a statement you make a little later (p. 17 on my printed
out version, where Table 3 is on p. 16), that summarizes where you stand:
"The 4-quadrants model clearly shows that the evolution of holons through
the holarchy of development is fully present in exteriors and can be validly
investigated from the exterior-surface perspective. The higher interior
realms not only show their footprints in the lower exterior ones but are
actually fully present in higher exterior worlds."
Exactly! In this quote, you come very close to saying what I'm
saying:
that the properties Wilber calls interior need not be placed on a second
axis distinct from exterior, but can go on the same axis, at a higher level
(or what I call stage on the same level). I go just one step further
though, saying that they are not only "fully present" in the higher exterior
worlds--they are identical to them. That is to say, in my model, the social
exterior holons, on any level of existence, are identical to the interior
individual holons on that same level.
This conclusion is bound to seem strange. I am saying that our
social
organizations and our mental phenomena are the same thing? The argument is
developed more fully in my book, but basically I contend that any holon can
look in three directions in the holarchy: down, at holons below itself; up,
at holons above itself; and horizontally, at holons in the same position as
itself. When we look down in the holarchy, at levels below us, we see what
we call objects or structures--tables, chairs, rocks, trees, cells, tissues,
and so on--and even our own physical bodies. These holons are perceived
"objectively", as external to us. When we look up in the holarchy, at the
stages (social organizations) above us, we see processes. These holons are
perceived subjectively, and as internal to us. Our thoughts, in other
words, represent perceptions of social holons. (Meditation, as an aside, is
the process of stopping or transcending thoughts, that is to say, moving
upward in the holarchy past these stages so that we are no longer below
them).
The Four Strands of Knowledge as Universal Holonic Interactions
To summarize my model of the holarchy, every level of existence has
fundamental or individual holons (atoms, cells, organisms), and social
holons (molecules, tissues, societies). The social holons are what Wilber
refers to as the social dimension or aspects of individual holons, and are
simultaneously the interior aspects of the individual holons, as the latter
see them. I would therefore recast your strands of knowledge as a series of
horizontal and vertical interactions among these holons. Trying to do that
in any detail is beyond the scope of this discussion, but I do want to
sketch out briefly a way in which your strands of knowledge might be
correlated with another set of relationships among holons. The latter are
fundamental to the entire holarchy, and thus such a correlation would give
real teeth to your claim that these strands of knowledge operate everywhere
in the holarchy, not just with humans (p. 5: "the Integral Cycle of
Knowledge also applies to the other levels in the ontological hierarchy and
not just the mental realms of science. The four strands flow through the
pre-mental, mental and post-mental ontologies and through all quadrants.")
In my holarchical model, I distinguish four basic properties of
holons:
assimilation, communication, adaptation and reproduction. All of these
properties are well-known to students of biology, of course, and in my book,
I argue that they can be observed at other levels besides the biological.
For example, an atom can assimilate an electron, communicate with another
atom, or adapt to an aqueous environment. This, too, has been noted by
others (e.g., Land 1973). Furthermore, at any level of existence, these
properties of holons can be defined in terms of their interactions with
other holons. Assimilation is an interaction of a holon with another holon
that is below it in the holarchy. Thus an atom assimilates an electron; a
cell assimilates a molecule; an organism assimilates tissue of a plant or
another organism. Communication is an interaction between two holons on the
same level: atoms (through chemical bonding), cells (through physical,
chemical or electrical interactions) and organisms can all communicate with
each other. Adaptation is an interaction between a holon at one level and a
higher-level holon (more precisely, a holon at a higher stage on the same
level). Atoms adapt to molecules they exist in, cells to tissues they
participate in, organisms to societies and other multi-holonic organizations
(e.g., ecosystems).
In my scheme of things, reproduction is a special property. Unlike
the
other three, it is not characteristic of social holons, but only of
individual holons. And of course, science tells us that atoms, which are
individual holons in my model, don't reproduce. But in any case,
reproduction in my model is a process involving all three of the other
processes simultaneously. I won't pursue the argument in detail--again,
it's in the book (Chapter 3)--but it's seen most clearly in the
reproduction of eukaryotic cells. Such cells reproduce by dividing, and
this is ordinarily done when they reach a certain maximum size. Hence,
reproduction is a form of assimilation, allowing the reproducing cell to
grow larger. But reproduction also involves communication with other cells
in the tissue, which must permit it to do so, and adaptation to the needs of
the entire tissue, which constrains the reproductive process according to
certain tissue-level rules. So one definition of reproduction is a process
in which assimilation, communication and adaptation all occur simultaneously
in a holon.
Now with that background, note that there appears to be a fairly
close
correspondence between these universal properties of holons and the strands
of knowledge. Apprehension is a form of assimilation, if we restrict the
former term to raw sensory impressions. Injunctions are mediated through
communication. Interpretation, I think, might be understood as a form of
adaptation, and validation as a form of reproduction. That is to say, when
an observation is validated, it is replicated by others, and this
replication necessarily involves the other three processes.
I want to emphasize again that this argument is put forth
tentatively; I
may be open to the charge of stretching analogies a bit. However, if we
continue this line of reasoning and accept that these correlations really do
exist, then a still further unification is apparent. This is because in
Worlds, I argue that all four of these fundamental properties of holons can
be understood as different manifestations of a single property or process.
I have already noted that reproduction can be understood as a process
involving each of the other three processes. It remains to be explained how
these latter three processes can be viewed as a single process. The key to
this lies in the understanding that how any particular property of a holon
appears depends on one's point of view, that is, the relationship of the
observer to the holon being observed. For example, earlier I gave as an
illustration of assimilation an atom capturing an electron. This is so from
the point of view of the atom. But from the electron's point of view, the
process is adaptation. When the electron interacts with the atom, its
behavior becomes constrained in certain ways. Furthermore, if the electron
that the atom assimilates belongs to another atom, a process of
communication--atomic bonding--is also occurring.
In summary, I'm arguing that every property of a holon involves some
kind
of interaction with holons above, below or on the same plane (stage or
level) as itself. By taking the point of view of these different holons, we
can see that what is called one type of property from one point of view is
the same as what we call another property as seen from another point of
view. If we now apply this same line of reasoning to the strands of
knowledge, we come to the conclusion that each strand, from a certain point
of view, may be perceived as some other strand. For example, the process by
which we apprehend data may be a process of interpretation for the holons
being apprehended. The process by which an injunction is delivered may,
from a holarchically higher point of view, be a process of apprehension. I
don't expect anyone to take such specific examples too seriously, but I
think the general thrust of the argument is clear: knowledge acquisition is
occurring at all levels of the holarchy, with a strand at one stage or level
corresponding to, indeed, identical to, another strand at another stage or
level. Still further, because this scheme links knowledge acquisition with
more general properties of holons, the process of acquiring knowledge can be
understood as a specific example or subset of the more general process of
growth in the holarchy. That is, knowledge is a kind of food that is
obtained and processed through various steps involving interactions among
different holons. This is not an original idea, of course. For example,
it was an important part of Gurdjieff's teachings (Ouspensky 1961). But we
now can describe this idea in the language of modern science and philosophy.
Before leaving this subject, I want to mention one more implication
of this
argument, which links knowledge acquisition closely to evolutionary theory
(as your quote from Popper on p. 7 suggests it should be). I argued earlier
that the validation process is a form of reproduction. What , exactly, is
being reproduced? A little thought, surely, indicates that the unit of
reproduction is what evolutionary biologists call a meme (Blackmore 1999).
A meme can be defined in various ways, but in my book (Chapter 9) I describe
it as a certain pattern of interactions between cells in the brain, or
between communicating human beings (usually but not always humans), with
both sets of interactions occuring in a closely correlated manner.
Reproduction of memes is the basis of what is commonly called cultural
evolution, but which I call evolution of social holons. In my holarchical
model, both Darwinian and "cultural" evolution occur on all levels of
existence, not simply the biological and the mental, respectively. Without
going into further details (see Chapter 9), it should be clear that by
defining validation as the process by which a meme is reproduced, knowledge
acquisition becomes firmly embedded into evolutionary theory.
Can the Transpersonal be Investigated or Interpreted from Lower Levels?
Having staked out the arguments for a one-scale model of holarchy,
then
traced some of the implications of this model for our understanding of the
four strands of knowledge, I now want to turn to some specific criticisms of
your paper. Most of these criticisms are directed against your claim that
knowledge of different levels of the holarchy can be obtained using methods
and/or interpretive frameworks that are based on other levels. Though as I
said before I generally accept this claim, when it's applied to
transpersonal phenomena, I think you may be overreaching.
For example, on p. 24 you assert that: "The refashioned Integral
Epistemology makes it possible for ordinary objective, monological
scientists of the mental/social realms to become explorers of the
transpersonal domains without ever needing to become contemplative
practitioners." I disagree. In my experience, and I believe not only
Wilber but many others will support me here, we can't, in our ordinary state
of consciousness, see the transpersonal at all. In my holarchical model,
that's because it exists on another level above us. Though I claimed
earlier that holons could look above themselves as well as below themselves,
their perception, in my model, has definite limits. Individuals can look at
the social stages above themselves, on their own level of existence, to the
extent that they participate in these stages. But they can't observe these
stages if they aren't part of them, and they can't observed the next level
of existence, which transcends all of these stages and organizes them into a
new form of existence, at all.
How, then, can researchers using monological methods study
transpersonal
phenomena? Your answer to this question is on p. 15: "A
researcher...could study, for example, the behaviour of several authentic
teachers of contemplative practice. She could record and and analyse their
private behavior, their scores on objective mental health tests and
standardised tests of cognitive development, their social interactions,
their brain wave patterns during meditation and during everyday activities,
their emotional responses, and their language patterns." This approach,
which in fact is what some researchers are now trying to do, has a critical
flaw in it, contained in the phrase "authentic teachers". Who is authentic?
A purely monological researcher has no way of knowing. She may ask
members of a spiritual community for help in making this decision, but that
merely pushes the problem back to another point: how does the researcher
know that these members are capable of judging who is authentic? How does
she know this community is genuine? There may be people who really do know,
but how can someone who doesn't know, who doesn't experience the
transpersonal, possibly identify them?
I believe we can all agree that this is, at the very least, a very
difficult practical problem. Much of the work attempting to correlate
physiology with higher consciousness that I am aware of is currently being
carried out by the Maharishi Institute in Fairfield, Iowa, whose members
believe (along with some other rather questionable ideas shared by their
current candidate for U.S. President, John Hagelin) that a few minutes of
meditation a day is sufficient to bring one enlightenment. In my thirty
years of experience, this simply is not true (a lesson I learned in a few
weeks a long time ago). Of course, some people may not believe me, but my
point is that many other people do agree with me, so already we have a major
problem in building a consensus on who is authentic, and therefore whose
studies we are going to accept.
In science, of course, practical problems like this are encountered
all the
time. The crux of the matter is whether this issue, given sufficient time
and effort, can be overcome. You apparently believe it can. I imagine your
response would go something like this: There are people who have genuinely
experienced higher consciousness, who have travelled some distance on the
path to experiencing it permanently. There are in fact probably people at
various levels or stages or distances along this path. These people can
come to a consensus about who is where, and make this information available
to people who consider themselves completely unable to judge. But again, I
disagree. In my experience (which is the only argument I can use here, a
position which itself underscores my point), people at one level of
consciousness cannot judge those above themselves. They can't say,
so-and-so has evolved to such-and-such. This means that not only can the
most advanced people not be recognized by a larger consensual group, but,
again, those on the monological bottom are truly lost.
What if we somehow could overcome this problem, and be certain that a
few
specific individuals were at a higher state of consciousness? Could a
monological approach then learn something useful about them? I'm not even
sure of that. One of the most important lessons I've learned--and again,
this is not an original one--is the importance of blending in with the
world, of appearing ordinary to other people. This is a vital necessity to
me, because I have learned--again, old lesson--that everything I do has an
effect on my consciousness. Getting too involved with the world creates a
lot of karma, which is to say, thoughts that have to be transcended. This
is not a problem that vanishes in a few years or decades, so I have to
believe that authentic subjects for any study of higher consciousness are
unlikely to reveal any unique behavioral attributes. The goal of the path
is not to be more intelligent, insightful, compassionate, whatever, than
others; it's to wake up. All of our efforts are directed towards this.
Yes, our intellects, emotions and bodies do gain new powers, but not, in my
experience, ones that are beyond the range of ordinary human beings. I
think Ken Wilber expressed this very well in Eye to Eye (1989), when he
remarked that he had never seen an enlightened master run a four-minute
mile, or produce a theory like Einstein's. (And even more insightfully,
Carlos Castaneda's Don Juan pointed out that becoming a warrior makes one
more vulnerable, not less).
What about physiological changes? Maybe, but again, I'm
skeptical. I
can only argue from my own experience, and I'm well aware people have no
reason to believe that I'm a very good example, but I have seen no changes
of the kind that would make a doctor, for example, raise his eyebrows. Much
has been claimed about correlations between brain wave activity and degree
of consciousness, but anyone who has ever tried to change her brainwaves
knows that there are lots of little tricks that can be learned in a fairly
short period of time. That, to me, is enough evidence that brainwaves are
useless as indicators of higher consciousness. I do feel that if there is
one candidate physiological parameter that has some promise as an indicator,
it would be energy metabolism in the brain, but even if this is so, I can
certainly imagine that there might be ways of altering this through habits
or practices not devoted to realizing higher consciousness.
I could go on and on about this subject, but the issue is obviously
complex, and open to a lot of debate. I'm sure studies like this are going
to increase, and I'm not really against them, because if I'm right, these
conclusions will eventually emerge, and if I'm wrong, I will be as curious
as anyone to see what some of these correlations are. But for now, and for
the foreseeable future, people carrying out this kind of research are going
to be subjected to a lot of criticism, entirely justifiable in my view, that
their subjects are not authentic. Because of this problem, I find some of
your examples in Table 3 questionable; they have the feel of data being
forced into your framework, to prove that there is a complete
interchangeability concerning methods, frameworks and focus of study at
different levels. I don't question that Wilhelm Reich, for example, had a
strong interest in the transpersonal, but that doesn't mean that his attempt
to interpret physiological studies from this point of view were valid.
Conversely, you list five investigators of the transpersonal domain who used
methodology or interpretation of another level. I think one can
legitimately argue that in some cases, these investigators, brillliant as
most or all of them may have been, were confusing the transpersonal with
other levels. To the extent that they were not, I would argue that they
were not really using a lower-level interpretative framework. I have great
respect for Stan Grof, for example, and I regard at least some of his
studies of the transpersonal genuine; that is, I believe some of his
subjects had genuine transpersonal experiences. But that doesn't compel me
to accept that his observations can be interpreted from a prenatal
framework, even if some of his subject also re-experienced this domain.
Maybe an example from my own experience will make this clearer. When
I
meditate under certain conditions, I am sometimes very much aware of
experiences from my early childhood. I can vividly see scenes, people, and
so forth that occurred a great many years ago. Since memories this vivid do
not present themselves to me except in what I regard as a fairly high state
of awareness, I could argue that there is some critical relationship between
my early years and the attempt to realize higher consciousness. But I don't
claim this, and frankly, until I became familiar with the Grof debate, it
never would have occurred to me to make this connection. The pathway to
higher consciousness breaks down all kinds of barriers in the mind, so it
seems logical to me that it sometimes might make very old memories
available. This would probably be even more true for Grof's subjects, using
drugs and other techniques which, though they may make the transpersonal
more accessible, may have many other, poorly understood, effects on the
brain. I can accept that if some of these memories are unpleasant--and in
the case of the birth experience, they surely are--some people might want
to, or even have to, deal with them in some way. But I don't accept that
this is necessary for everyone, or that everyone must even relive such
experiences. The name of the game is suffering, but there are many ways to
do that (and the devil is always inventing new ones).
Another example of where you seem to force data to fit into your
general
scheme is in your argument that every level of existence has a paradoxical
nature. This, again is a point important to your contention that every type
of approach to knowledge acquisition can be applied to every level of the
holarchy. In Table 4 you present examples of paradoxes at different levels.
As a trained molecular biologist, I find nothing paradoxical about the
statement "The genetic information of the whole is contained in each part
(the cell)." Science has a very good understanding of how genes work, and
while there are to be sure still some major mysteries surrounding
embryogenesis or biological development, there is nothing paradoxical about
this process. The term "paradoxical" is not, of course, synonomous with
"not understood". Likewise, there is nothing paradoxical to my
understanding in the statement "The individual organism sustains the ecology
of the whole." Ecosystems to a greater or lesser extent are dependent on
their composition of individual organisms (though in Worlds, I review data
suggesting that in most cases a single species is not critical to the
stability of an ecosystem). So what? An airplane, as ecologists Paul and
Ann Ehrlich (1981) pointed out in a famous metaphor, is sustained by its
individual rivets. Is that paradoxical?
I understand completely why you are trying to find paradoxes at these
levels of existence. True paradoxes do exist at or near the ends of the
holarchy, in quantum effects and in transpersonal phenomena. We would like
to show that paradox, too, is found throughout the holarchy. But I don't
believe that it is, or that we should expect it to be. It's found in the
transpersonal levels, because we are confronting something above or beyond
our logical mind. Why it exists in the quantum world, I don't know, though
I suspect it may have something to do with the fact that this world is not
just below our own, but very far below. In Worlds, there is considerable
discussion about how our perception of other holons depends on our
relationship to them in the holarchy.
I do believe that there is a lot of truth in your statement, "paradox
lies
at the core of each event whether that be physical, psychological or
spiritual" (p. 18). But this universal occurrence of paradox, it seems
pretty clear to me, is rooted in the paradox of consciousness. Science at
all levels makes certain core assumptions, including the independence of the
observer from the observed, and the validity of inductive processes, which
science itself can't prove. These problems in turn reflect, in holarchical
thinking, the fact that we are in particular position in the holarchy, and
therefore do not have access to the entire holarchy. In this important
sense, all our observations are paradoxical and incomplete. But this
doesn't mean that there are paradoxes specific to particular phenomena at
every level of existence.
Ironically, given your desire to achieve a unity in the holarchy, to
demonstrate the existence of common themes at every level--an aim I share
with you and which probably leads me astray sometimes, too--you do not see
this unity in a place where I do. On p. 14, you state: "In the final
stages of evolution the boundaries that have divided the inner and the outer
world and the personal and collective worlds become more permeable and less
restrictive, and there is a more intimate engagement between self and other
and between the individual and the collective." In my holarchical model,
this dissolution of boundaries does not appear just at the final stage,
though if there is such a thing, one would presume it is most final and
complete there. It occurs at every new level of existence. When prebiotic
molecules organized into a cell, self and other broke down, as previously
separate and somewhat independent holons became unified. This cell then
became an other to neighboring cells, until this self-other distinction was
dissolved in the organism. In my holarchical model, each level of existence
has several stages, where holons become differentiated, and the self-other
distinction becomes greatest. When these stages organize into a new level,
otherness vanishes, until this new level begins to differentiate. (Captured
so long ago in the Hindu Creation myth of the God who looked around and
became lonely; though that is usually cited as a description of involution,
or stepping down from the Ultimate, it's a pretty fair overvew of an
essential theme in evolution). As I discuss in Worlds, this surely is the
basis of Wilber's pre-trans fallacy (Wilber 1989). If young children and
people of earlier cultures seem to have some of the features of
enlightenment, it's because they are enlightened--relative to the biological
level from which they are just emerging. But the enlightenment pursued by
an adult human being is that realized by transcending the mental level, and
so is higher.)
One final example of what I view as your attempt to try to force data
into
your scheme is on p. 24, where you state "The conversion experience is
real." Your point is that people of mainstream religions have genuine
spiritual experiences, but don't understand them correctly because of the
faulty interpretive framework laid upon them by their religous
organizations. I can accept that there is some truth to this--and to the
extent that there is, your view has great and admirable potential for
bringing people of different religions together--but I believe that the
majority of religious experiences , and associated conversions, have very
little to do with genuine contact with higher consciousness. I have talked
to individuals who have claimed to have such experiences, and frankly, I
find almost no "experience" in their claims at all--nothing at all that
could be used as a basis for common understanding, which surely would not be
the case if they had some taste of a higher world. (Yes, their response
would be that I'm the one ignorant of God--my view is certainly not one that
brings all of us together). Most of these people, as far as I can tell, are
told beforehand what it is they are supposed to feel, and then manage to
deceive themselves that they have. I don't doubt they have felt some
emotion, often powerful, but there is a big difference between emotions and
a state in which, ultimately, emotions are transcended. (This leads into
the question of which of Wilber's stages of human development can have
access to the higher levels, which is beyond the scope of this discussion).
Conclusions: Stages and Levels, The Interior and the Social
I don't regard these criticisms as very serious, relative to what you
have
accomplished. I'm much more interested in the implications of the
four-strand model for unifying knowledge acquisition with other aspects of
the holarchy, and I have tried to point a direction here in which
unification efforts should proceed. Like you, I maintain great respect for
Ken Wilber, whose works are hardly diminished by what either of us have to
say. Indeed, I think a one-scale view may help buttress some other
weaknesses of his model. For example, it has been pointed out by several of
his critics that some of Wilber's levels, such as cognitive stages in human
development, do not genuinely transcend lower levels, such as the body and
emotions (Goddard 1997). While Wilber, if I understand his latest thinking
in this debate correctly, has tried to address this problem by bringing in a
new distinction, between permanent and temporary structures, these
differences in relationships, I believe, can be much more easily understood
in a model which recognizes that there are both stages and levels of
existence. In my holarchical model, stages transform, but do not transcend,
the stages below them, whereas one level does transcend that level, and all
its stages, below it. Thus human cognitive phenomena, as part of one or
more stages on the mental level of existence, do not transcend the emotions
or even the body, which is the first or fundamental stage on this level.
That this arrangement is not simply an ad hoc way of fitting the data is
made clear by the observation that a very analogous relationship is observed
on lower levels of existence--tissues vs. cells, and large molecules vs.
atoms. As discussed at length in Worlds, biological molecules do not
transcend atoms, whereas cells do. Likewise, biological tissues do not
transcend cells, whereas organisms do. Close examination of these levels,
which we obviously can study much more objectively than our own, in fact
reveals new insights into just what the terms transformation and
transcendence mean.
Nevertheless, while I believe my one-scale holarchical model removes
the
necessity of Wilber's four-quadrant divisions, I do recognize distinctions
between social and individual holons, which I regard as the basis of a
distinction between interior and exterior qualities or properties. I
understand that Ken has had very good reasons for emphasizing interior
qualities, for many scientists and some philosophers do tend to overlook or
at least underestimate them. Though I place them on the same scale as
exterior qualities, it should be apparent from where I put them that I am
not ignoring or trying to collapse them--any more than by developing the
idea of holarchy itself, any of us is saying that all forms of life are one
and the same. And yet, from some point of view perhaps they are, and as the
holarchy is further developed, I expect it will increasingly reflect this
point of view.
References
Blackmore, S. (1999) The Meme Machine. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Chalmers, D. (1996) The Conscious Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Ehrlich, P. A. and A. H. Ehrlich (1981) Extinction: The Causes and
Consequences of the Disappearance of Species. New York: Random House.
Goddard, G. (1997) "Airing our Transpersonal Differences".
Land, G. (1973) Grow or Die. New York: Random House.
Ouspensky, P. D. (1961) In Search of the Miraculous. New York: Harcourt
Brace Jovanovich.
Wilber, K. (1989) Eye to Eye. Boston: Shambhala.
Wilber, K. (1995) Sex, Ecology, Sprituality. Boston: Shambhala.
Homepage of Andrew Smith
|