An independent forum for a critical discussion of the integral philosophy of Ken Wilber
From 1993 to 2003
Elías-Manuel Capriles-Arias filled the Chair of Eastern Studies at the Faculty of Humanities and Education, University of The Andes, Mérida, Venezuela (originally ascribed to the Dean's Office and then to the Department of Philosophy). Thereafter he has been ascribed to the Center of Studies on Africa and Asia, School of History, same Faculty and University, where he teaches Philosophy and elective subjects on the problems of globalization, Buddhism, Asian Religions and Eastern Arts.
Besides teaching at the University, Capriles is an instructor of Buddhism and Dzogchen certified by the Tibetan Master of these disciplines, Chögyal Namkhai Norbu; in this field, he has taught in Venezuela, Peru, Spain and Costa Rica. See his
personal website here.
SEE MORE ESSAYS WRITTEN BY ELIAS CAPRILES
Some Preliminary
Comments on Wilber V
Elias Capriles
The
repeated, overwhelming tsunamis of criticism Wilber has received from a series
of theorists denouncing what they view as a mistaken perspective or as major
errors, might well be among the reasons that led him to undertake, in the first
decade of the twenty-first century, an ongoing, radical reshaping of his
theories that is giving rise to that which he (e.g. Wilber, 2010) himself has
agreed to label Wilber V.
This
new Wilber no longer posits either the famed Great Chain of Being, or a series
of planes of existence, or the thesis that the world emanated from a
supramundane source, or the view that higher spiritual levels can only be
steadily attained and gone through after a significant degree of progress has
been reached along different lines of development, or the supposed
impossibility of “jumping” from a low to a high spiritual level. In the same
way, his evolutionary view has shifted to a here-now perspective having as its
base Sheldrake’s (1981) theories—which Wilber formerly rejected—of
morphogenetic fields and formative causation. However, he retains and further
develops his and Don Back’s version of spiral dynamics as a paradigm of human
evolution, producing a new version of his structural evolutionary model
(diagram and exposition in Wilber, 2007) that,
like the preceding ones, involves a series of lines of development with rungs
running parallel or nearly parallel in all or some of them, and continues to
establish a (now looser) parallel between ontogeny and phylogenesis.
Let
us consider the first ontogenic line of development in Wilber V, which is the
cognitive one. This line has as its lowest rung the sensorymotor; as its second
rung, the preoperational / symbolic; as its third rung, the preoperational /
conceptual; as the fourth, the concrete operational; as the fifth, the formal
operational; and as the sixth, that of early vision-logic, categorized as
metasystemic. These six, and the stages at the same level in the other lines,
are located in the first tier of the above-mentioned diagram. The seventh rung
is the one that he names middle vision-logic and categorizes as paradigmatic,
and the eighth is the one he calls late vision-logic and categorizes as
cross-paradigmatic—which together occupy the second tier. Then the ninth is the
one called global mind, which corresponds to what he previously called the
psychic level; the tenth is that of meta-mind, which is no other than what he
formerly called the subtle level; as the eleventh, that of overmind,
corresponding to what he previously called the causal level; and as a twelfth,
in place of the nondual, the one he now calls the supermind (a term probably
drawn from Śrī Aurobindo). These four higher rungs are placed in the
third tier.
A
second line of development is the Graves-inspired one that he calls values /
spiral dynamics, having as a first rung, on the right, one that is centered on
survival and that is at the same level of the first rung of the first line; as
a second rung on the right, what he calls the kin spirits, corresponding to the
first rung on the left, which is the one he calls magic-animistic—both of which
are the level of the second rung in the first line; as a third rung on the
right what he calls the power gods, corresponding to the second rung on the
left, which is the one he calls egocentric—both of which are the level of the
third rung in the first line; as a fourth rung on the right what he calls the
truth force, corresponding to the third rung on the left, which is the one he
calls absolutistic—both of which are at the level of the fourth rung in the
first line; as a fifth rung on the right that which he is calling the strive
drive, corresponding to the fourth rung on the left, which is the one he calls
multiplistic—both of which are at the level of the fifth rung in the first
line; as a sixth rung on the right what he calls the human bond, corresponding
to the fifth rung on the left, which is the one he calls relativistic—both of
which are at the level of the sixth rung in the first line; as a seventh rung
on the right the one he calls flex-flow, which is at the level of the seventh
rung in the first line; and as an eighth rung on the right the one he calls
global view, which is at the level of the eighth rung in the first line—with
what he calls the systemic as the sixth rung on the left, placed between the
corresponding seventh and eighth rungs of both the first line and the right of
the second line (this second line hence not reaching beyond the eighth level of
the first line, and thus not reaching the third tier).
The
third line is the Kegan-inspired one of orders of consciousness, beginning with
Orders 0, 1st, 2d, 3d, 4th and 4.5,
which are, respectively, at the level of the six lower stages of the first line
and of the right side of the second line, and ending with the 5th
Order, which lies at the level of the eighth stage of both the first line and
the right of the second line. This line thus does not reach the third tier.
The
fourth is the Loevinger/Cook/Greuter-inspired line of self-identity that
includes eight rungs referred to as symbiotic, impulsive, self-protective,
conformist, conscientious, individualistic, autonomous and integrated, which
are at the level of the eight lower rungs of the first line and the right of
the second line, followed by an ninth stage, called construct-aware—at the
level of global mind in the first line—and a final, tenth stage, called
ego-aware—which lies at the level of meta-mind on the first line. The last two
rungs are within the third tier.
The
fifth is the Gebser-inspired line of worldviews, which goes from the archaic
(at the level of the first rung of lines one, three and four, as well as of the
right of the second line) through the magic (between the second and third rungs
of the first, third and fourth lines, and of the right of the second line), the
mythic, the rational and the pluralistic (at the level of the fourth, firth and
sixth rungs of the first, third and fourth lines, as well as of the right of
the second line, respectively), up to the integral (at the level of the
systemic on the left of the second line). This line does not reach into the
third tier.
Finally,
the sixth is the Fowler-inspired line of stages of faith, going from (0) the
one he calls undifferentiated (at the level of the first rung of the first,
third, fourth and fifth lines, as well as of the right of the second line),
through (1) the magical (at the level of the second rung of the first, third
and fourth lines, as well as the right of the second line), (2) the
mythic-literal (at the level of the third rung of the first, third and fourth
lines, as well as of the right of the second line), (3) the conventional (at
the level of the fourth rung of the first, third and fourth lines, as well as
of the right of the second line—which as already noted are at the level of the
third rung of the fifth line), (4) the individual-reflexive (at the level of
the fifth rung of the first, third and fourth lines, as well as of the right of
the second line, and at the level of the fourth rung of the fifth line), (5)
the conjunctive (at the level of the sixth rung of the first, third and fourth
lines, as well as of the right of the second line, and of the fifth rung of the
fifth line), and (6) the universalizing-commonwealth, which is at the level of
the systemic at the left of the second line and of the integral on the fifth
line. Hence this line does not reach into the third tier either.
Thus
it is clear that, even though now Wilber admits there may be a somehow freer
transit between lower and higher levels, and that development along one line
does not need to strictly depend on development along the other lines, he still
adheres to a rigid schema of hierarchical structures of the kind denounced
throughout this book, which as such, just like those in his previous
elaborations, does not correspond to any ancient, traditional system—Buddhist
or non-Buddhist—and that he continues to mistakenly identify some of the rungs
in at least one of the lines with stages of spiritual development posited and
charted by higher Buddhist and other traditional systems, even though, as shown
above in this chapter, they do not correspond to any Buddhist schema, and no
Buddhist system has ever posited all-embracing evolutionary schemas. Moreover,
he continues to posit a correspondence among the rungs in the various lines,
viewing them as stages in an overall, integral type of development—which,
furthermore, he now presents as development from lower to higher focal points (cakra)
that he associates to different colors in a schema which, as M. Alan Kazlev
(undated) notes, is not found in any traditional system. Kazlev writes (ibidem):
[The
schema in question] is not much more that about thirty years old; the earliest
reference I know of is Christopher Hills’ (1977) Nuclear Evolution; an
elaborate Integral theory that predates Wilber’s AQAL by several decades…
Hills’ book seems to have had little or no influence on the wider world, so
Wilber’s rainbow chakras are probably based on pop-Osho New Age websites.
Even
though the fact that he carried out this radical reshaping of his system
amounts to acknowledging that he was altogether wrong in so much of what he
formerly asserted, in one of the Integral Life Newsletters of the last months
of 2010 Wilber wrote that in spite of it he has always been right! It is
to be assumed, thus, that what in his view has always been right is the concept
that development occurs along different lines of development, in a rigid
structural schema in which advancement along the different lines is to a
considerable extent interdependent, and his association of the four highest
levels to the four kāyas of higher Buddhist systems.
In
spite of the above, I deem it praiseworthy that Wilber is trying to correct at
least one of what here (as well as in many other works by different theorists)
I have denounced as one of his key errors, by calling for a naturalistic turn
to religion and introducing the concept of intra-physical. With regard to the
former, it is not clear to me how this would differ from a return to what in
my view (not in Wilber’s, as he continues to uphold a rigid, modern,
progress-oriented view of our spiritual and social evolution) religion was
before the otherworldly turning that gave birth to the gods. With regard to the
latter, Frank Visser (undated) questions:
Is intra-physical a
physical concept? Then no physicist would subscribe to that notion. Or is it metaphysical?
Then what’s the point of calling all this “post-metaphysical”? Isn’t all
science supposed to be “post-metaphysical”? So what’s the big deal then? And if
he introduces the notion of “intra-physical”, that surely introduces ontology
in its wake? For Wilber, “post-metaphysical” primarily seems to refer to
“evidence-based”, compared to speculative. If that’s the case, it’s an
unfortunate label for a view that explores other experiential avenues than the
bodily senses alone.
Wilber
V, and most of those who have discussed the latest Wilber so far, under the
spell of so-called postmodern thought, frown on whatever may be categorized as
ontology. In order to determine whether or not this is justified, let us
consider some crucial turnabouts in the recent history of Western philosophy.
Descartes produced his metaphysics in reaction to the objections to the
supposed certainty of knowledge raised by modern skeptics, and in particular by
the nouveaux pyrrhoniens
(Popkin, 1979), as these challenged his religious and metaphysical
certainties—thus having the potential to make him experience ontological
anxiety and even panic—and could also be used to undermine the project,
so dear to him, of achieving technological dominion over the universe through
the development of science (Capriles, 1994). His strategy to attempt to make
his system immune to skeptic criticism, consisted in applying the skeptic
method of methodic doubt until he would find a truth that could not be doubted,
which he wrongly believed to have found in the intuition of what he called the cogito—a
mere phenomenon, produced by the delusory valuation of the threefold thought
structure, which is one of the poles of the basic structure that is the second
aspect of avidyā in the division favored by Longchen Rabjampa, and
which nonetheless Descartes wrongly posited as a God-created, nonspatial substance
(since this intuition could not found the world’s external existence, he had to
resort to the Christian God to found it).
Among
the works of moderate skeptics who reacted against the new developments of
metaphysics, Hume’s shook Immanuel Kant’s naïve substantiation of his
metaphysical convictions, though not so these convictions themselves.
Therefore, though the German metaphysician latter claimed that his reading of
the Scottish critical empiricist awakened him from his dogmatic dream,
what actually happened was that it forced him to express his dogmatic
metaphysics in a new way, in an attempt to give the false impression that he
was respecting the limits of knowledge and thus producing a “true science” (for
an explanation of how he breached the limits in question, cf. Capriles, 1994,
2007a Vol. I).
The
widespread realization of Kant’s failure in his purported attempt to produce a
metaphysics that would respect the limits inherent in human knowledge, gave
rise to the characteristically modern project of positivism, the best-known
forms of which intended to surpass metaphysics, ontology and whatever else has
traditionally gone under the label philosophy by keeping to verifiable evidence
of the kind that would be acceptable to the positive sciences. Among the
different brands of positivism, August Compte’s intended to replace ontology
and the rest of what traditionally went under the name philosophy, with an encyclopædia
of positive sciences; the Austrian empirio-criticists produced a science-based
critical philosophy that, like Alfred North Whitehead’s metaphysics (which was
intended to surpass, by the same token, all of the classic dualisms of
metaphysics, and substantialistic monism), involved an ontology free
from the mind-matter dualism; the neopositivists, including those in the Vienna
Circle, circumscribed philosophy to a critical philosophy of science; some
trends of philosophy of language (not Ludwig Wittgenstein’s final system, as it
asserted language not to match reality and to be a source of delusion[i]) circumscribed
the ambit of philosophy to determining whether or not statements are
meaningful; etc.
However,
in our time all forms of positivism are widely seen as obsolete remnants of the
enthusiasm with science proper to early modernity; in particular, even though
most of those philosophers who define themselves as postmodern continue to
uphold the myth of progress that is the root and essence of modernity, in their
majority they outright negate that the discourses of science and philosophy can
achieve the ideal of adæquatio intellectus et rei (i.e., concordance
with a supposedly independent, factic reality). In fact, this idea runs
counter, not only to the trends of philosophy that define themselves as
postmodern, but to the views of a long list of thinkers that includes
philosophers, scientists and philosopher-scientists, and that goes at least as
back as the Greek Skeptics.
It
was noted that Kant claimed that the Scottish critical empiricist, David Hume,
had awakened him from what his “dogmatic dream.” Among Hume’s alleged
discoveries, most relevant to us at this point is the universally accepted
objection to empirical science as the source of “scientific laws” that nowadays
is widely referred to as Hume’s law, and which may be enunciated as follows:
“we are not entitled to extrapolate the regularities observed in a limited
number of cases to the totality of possible cases, thus making it into a law, as
one or more of the unobserved cases could contradict the supposed law.”
Furthermore, science claims to derive its alleged laws from the observation of
objective facts, when in truth the scientists’ observations are, as Bachelard
made it clear (1957) and as so many others have reiterated,[ii] utterly
conditioned by their expectations—and therefore by their ideologies and wishful
thinking. An anecdote from Edgar Morin (1981a) clearly illustrates the extent
to which observational judgments are conditioned by ideology: while driving his
car into a crossroads, he saw how the driver of another car disregarded the
traffic light and with the front of his car hit a moped moving with the green
light. Morin stopped his car and stepped down in order to testify in favor of
the moped driver, yet when he did so he heard the latter admit that it was him
who overlooked the red light and hit the car on the side. Incredulous, the
famed thinker examined the car, finding the dent the moped made in the car to
be on the latter’s side, and concluded that his socialist ideology and thirst
for social justice caused him to perceive the event wrongly and invert the
facts, even though he had not drunk any alcohol and there were no other
conditions that could have distorted his perception. In the case of an
experiment planned beforehand, the results are even more doubtful, for the way
in which the experiment is set and the criteria in terms of which the data are
evaluated are arranged to satisfy the researcher’s expectations, as he or she intends
to corroborate a theory set forth beforehand.
The
above explains why such a conservative thinker as Karl Popper (1961) noted
that, if no experience contradicts a theory, scientists are entitled to adopt
it provisionally as a probable truth (thus open-mindedly
acknowledging that no scientific theory can be fully substantiated, yet
closed-mindedly clinging to the belief in truth qua adequætio), and that
the acceptance of a new theory gives rise to as many problems as it solves.
Moreover, as it is well-known, on going through the history of science, Thomas
Kuhn (1970) noted that from the moment a scientific theory or paradigm is
accepted as true, scientific observations begin to contradict it, yet the
scientists consistently overlook these contradictions until the point at which
they become so abundant and conspicuous that they can no longer ignore them,
and hence they set out to devise new theories and paradigms in order to account
for these observations—yet new observations will contradict the new theory or
paradigm as well and hence the process in question will repeat itself again and
again.
In
the Genealogy of Morals, Friedrich Nietzsche (1999) had already
surpassed the above-discussed idea that our interpretations often do not
reflect facts, and had gone so far as to claim that there are no facts that may
be or not be matched by our interpretations. Gianni Vattimo (1995, p. 50), in
his “postmodern” period (in which he propounded the active radicalization of
nihilism), wrote in this regard:
Nihilism
means in Nietzsche “de-valorization of the supreme values” and fabulation of
the world: there are no facts, only interpretations, and this is also an
interpretation.
All
of the above shows that Georges Sorel (2d. Ed. 1922, 1906, 1908) was right in
claiming, between the last years of the nineteenth century and the onset of the
twentieth century, that human beings act under the influence of myths, that the
sciences are myths, and that the scientific pretensions of Marxism—a focus of
his criticism—responded to the force of the myth of science, which prevailed in
Marx’s time.[iii]
And that Antonio Gramsci (1998, p. 63)[iv] was equally
right in pointing out, in 1948, that to the extent to which we take the
“discoveries” of the sciences as truths in the sense of adæquatio of a
scientific map to an interpreted territory, the sciences are ideologies. In
fact, science and technology are indivisible from the ideological project of
modernity,[v]
which initially was associated with the ascending bourgeoisie and at a later
stage, through the influence of Marxism, also with the ascending proletariat:
as Marcuse [1964] noted, science is by its nature instrumental, and hence it
naturally delivers the means for the domination of the natural environment and
other human beings.[vi] Thus it is not
difficult to see why Michel Foucault (1976, 1978) and Gilles Deleuze (1980)[vii] asserted
philosophy and science to be more than ideologies: for a very long time
philosophical systems, and for a shorter time scientific disciplines and
theories (according to Deleuze, psychoanalysis playing this role at the time he
wrote the book in question), have functioned as an “abstract machine or
generalized axiomatic” that works as the matrix that makes possible the very
existence of power—their function being that of providing power with the forms
of knowledge necessary to sustain the models on the basis of which it will have
to structure itself in each period. Finally, the belief that science discovers
truths was demystified to such an extent that Paul K. Feyerabend (1982, 1984,
1987)—who showed scientists to often arrive at their discoveries and theories by
breaking the procedural rules of science—placed Western reason and science
on the same plane as magic and sorcery.
I
would not deny that, in spite of Hume’s law and the whole of the above
objections, the sciences are as a rule capable of predicting some types of
events with a considerable degree of reliability, as well as of producing
predictable immediate effects. However, in the long run they produce
effects that altogether contradict the ones they claim to be intent on
producing. In fact, as noted in the preceding chapter, in terms of the
semantics of Alfred Korzybski (1973),
according to which sanity is determined by the
structural fit between our reactions to the world and what is actually going on
in the world, and insanity by the lack of such fit, we must conclude that Śākyamuni Buddha was right when he compared fully fledged avidyā
to an illness, and that Candrakīrti hit
the mark when he compared this fully fledged avidyā
to insanity, for it gives rise to a severe structural
discrepancy between our reactions to the world and what is actually going on in
the world: as stated again and again throughout this book, our attempts to
achieve satisfaction yield dissatisfaction, our efforts to suppress pain
produce pain, and our efforts to destroy death and all negative aspects of life
and build a technological Eden have originated the ecological crisis that is
producing major natural disasters and which threatens to disrupt human society
and put an end to human existence in the course of the present century. It thus
seems that Korzybski was wrong when, in terms of the famed map-territory
analogy, noted that the map is not the territory, yet claimed that the map
could be correct in the sense of having a structure similar to that of the
territory that allows us to successfully deal with the latter, thus achieving
the structural fit defining sanity.
Korzybski’s criterion coincides with the one that, in
the face of Hume’s law and the accumulated objections of subsequent
epistemologists (cf. Capriles, 1994, 2007a vol. III, 2007c), Alfred Julius Ayer (1981) devised with the aim of
validating the sciences: the one according to which “we are authorized to have
faith in our procedure, so long as it carries out its function, which is that
of predicting future experience and thus control our environment.” However, in
trying to control our environment with the purported aim of creating an
artificial Eden and kill death and pain, the sciences and the technology based
on them, rather than achieving their declared effect,[viii] have produced
a hellish chaos and taken us to the brink of extinction—and, moreover, at no
moment did they foresee this outcome. Therefore Ayer’s criterion, rather than validating, outright invalidates the
sciences.
In
fact, as already noted, the current ecological crisis, which unless radical
change is achieved in both the human psyche and society will disrupt the latter
within the current century and likely lead to the extinction of our species
within the same period, has made it evident that the technological application
of the sciences in the long run gives rise to effects contrary to the ones they
are allegedly intended to produce. Thus to the extent to which the sciences
involve a pretension of truth in the sense of exact correspondence of their
maps to the territory of the given, as well as the pretension of improving our
lives and producing a technological paradise, it is clear that they are
metanarratives involving the denial of their character as metanarratives, and
as such they must be denounced as being both myths and ideologies: they are
elements of modernity’s myth of progress,[ix]
which ecological crisis has proved, not merely to be unrealizable, but to be
outright deadly. (A lengthier discussion of this subject is featured in
Capriles [2007a, Vol. III]; my initial discussion of the subject appeared in
Capriles [1994] and there is an ample discussion of it in the Introduction to
Capriles [under evaluation by publishers]).
The
above discussion of the limits of science makes it evident that the
positivistic belief that metaphysics will be surpassed and truth will be
attained by replacing philosophy with the positive sciences (etc.) could hardly
be more erroneous. However, in the first half of the twentieth century, there
were attempts to surpass metaphysics in ways that were very different from
positivism’s—among which at this point it is imperative to discuss the ones
made by Edmund Husserl and those who, after him, continued to develop
phenomenology. Rather than reacting to Kant’s inconsistencies with a rejection
of ontology, Husserl—who called his phenomenology an “absolute positivism” (one
that was concerned with essences relevant for ontology rather than with
observed facts relevant for science and technology)—and the rest of
twentieth-century phenomenologists set out to produce an ontology based
exclusively on that which appears
in experience, which, they believed, as such would be free from unfounded
metaphysical theses. However, although for decades phenomenology enjoyed the
highest prestige, nowadays it is widely acknowledged that it fell short of its
purported aim.
One
of the noted philosophers who made the greatest impact on denouncing this fact
was Jacques Derrida (1967), who asserted phenomenology to be no more than a [crypto]-metaphysics, while branding the
phenomenological emphasis on the supposed immediacy of experience as the “new
transcendental illusion.” I endorse Derrida’s assertion, except for one detail,
which I discuss in the note appended at the end of this sentence.[x]
However, the reason why I view phenomenology as a cryptometaphysics and the
belief in the immediacy of experience as an illusion springing from an error
analogous to the one that according to Kant gave rise to the “transcendental
illusion,” is particular to my own perspective. The problem, for me, is that
basing ontology exclusively on that which appears in human
experience is no guarantee that metaphysical constructs will not slip into it,
for in saṃsāra, to which human experience pertains,
fully-fledged avidyā causes us to experience being as given,
unquestionable, uneradicable, and somehow absolute; the
mental subject as being in its own right and hence as a substance,
and as the thinker of thought, the doer of action and the experiencer
of experience; the essents we face as being in their own right and
thus as constituting a series of different substances; etc. Hence an
ontology elaborated on the basis of samsaric experience alone would not be
really free from metaphysical fictions, as it is most likely to feature at
least some of the ones just mentioned—given, inherent, somehow
absolute being; a substantial cogito inherently separate from the
physical world and even from the human individual’s experiences, thoughts and
acts; countless external, physical substances—and probably many other ones.
The
above is what in general occurred with twentieth-century phenomenology. The core phenomena of fully-fledged avidyā / léthe
that seem most outstanding as inadvertent metaphysical foundations in the
system built by the trend’s originator, Edmund Husserl,
and which he took for given, ineradicable substances, were the
pseudo-absolute Cartesian cogito and the noetic-noematic (subject-object)
schism that is the condition of possibility of the cogito and the axis
of dualistic, allegedly immediate, yet actually mediated samsaric experience.
Martin Heidegger found Husserl’s departure from metaphysics insufficient and
set to carry it as far as he deemed it necessary, whereas Jean-Paul Sartre and
others of those who received Heidegger’s influence set to go beyond
Heidegger—yet both Heidegger and Sartre, like
the bulk of twenty-century phenomenologists, failed to go beyond metaphysics,
for both of them failed to realize that we are completely deluded and
that the phenomenon of being that pervades our experience is no more
than a deceptive appearance manifesting in our experience that constitutes a
pivotal aspect of our delusion, and thus kept taking being to be given, somehow
absolute, unquestionable and uneradicable (in fact, as I have shown in
depth elsewhere [Capriles, 2007a Vol. I], Heidegger reduced Heraclitus’
concepts of léthe and alétheia,
and hence the dialectics between the respective conditions, to such as shallow
level as to make them insignificant).
Heidegger,
in particular, under the spell of delusion, overlooked the fact that the true nature of reality, since it cannot be
included in a class wider than itself and does not exclude anything, has
neither proximate gender nor specific difference, and
hence cannot be contained in any concept, including those of being, nonbeing,
both and neither. And since being is the foundation of the whole of our
delusive experience, which he mistakenly took to be given and undeluded,
he made the logical mistake of equating it with the
true nature of reality. Furthermore, although he rightly identified
being with the phenomenon of being that pervades all of the experience that phenomenologists
deemed immediate but that is actually mediated, he failed to realize the
phenomenon in question to be one of the most basic aspects of the fundamental
human delusion rather than being the true, unquestionable Base of the whole of
reality.
On his part, Sartre seemed to have mistakenly, metaphysically
assumed that there was a given, absolute being distinct from the phenomenon
of being,[xi]
and, like Husserl, to have assumed the subject-object duality in experience to
be given and as such uneradicable. However, in spite of this, and of
Derrida’s charges that in his interpretation and usage of Heidegger’s concepts
he incurred in psychologism and anthropocentrism, the noted
French existentialist had invaluable insights that
can greatly contribute to the production of the philosophy required by our
time. Among other things, he clearly showed the cogito not to be a
substance (as I have shown elsewhere,[xii] by the same token providing us with the tools for
elucidating the concept of svasaṃvittiḥ / svasaṃvedana
/ awareness [of] consciousness as elaborated by Dharmakīrti on the basis
of the findings of Dignāga, and how it is related with the Dzogchen
concept of rangrig
or svasaṃvedana); he asserted human
existence to be drawn toward the holon—his definition of which may be
validly applied to Awakening (so that the meaning he gave the term is radically
different from Koestler’s [1967; Koestler & Smythies, 1970])—as télos, in
such a way that all human actions, thoughts and so on were carried out in the
hope of achieving the condition in question (which, however, he deemed it
impossible to attain); and he dismounted the pseudo-unity of the Dasein
into its constitutive elements, in a way that may be very profitable to
Dzogchen practitioners. (For an in-depth discussion
of all of this cf. Capriles, 2007a Vol. I.)
After phenomenology’s abortive attempts to produce a
nonmetaphysical ontology, Derrida, claiming to have
found the sketching of an end of ontology in Nietzsche, Lacan’s Freud and
Levinas, undertook what he deemed to be a destruction of metaphysics which,
unlike the one Heidegger pretended to have achieved, would be genuine and
thorough, and which would bring ontology to an end and by the same token open a
perspective in which that which he called différance[xiii] would find a
place. He believed the way to achieve this to consist in abstaining from the
production of ontological elaborations and circumscribing the task of philosophy
to the deconstruction
of existing discourses—and in particular of all totalizing
metanarratives, which had been a target of the so-called postmodern
trend ever since Jean-François Lyotard’s (1979) La condition postmoderne
introduced this defective label. However, this would be of no use, for
fully-fledged avidyā produces an experiential ontological confusion
that consists in perceiving phenomena that are in the process of being (essents) as being
inherently and absolutely, in their own right (without depending on
anything else)—and though this ontological confusion cannot be brought to an
end by merely intellectual means, in order to undertake the spiritual practices
necessary to undo it, one must have understood what is the confusion to be
eradicated and why it is a confusion rather than the undistorted experience of
the true condition of reality, as ordinary people take it to be: this is the
reason why ontology has been a central aspect of all genuine forms of Buddhism,
Taoism, Shaivism and other systems I deem conducive to Awakening, and must
continue to be so.
The
above is one of the main reasons why, as stated in various of my works (most
thoroughly in Capriles, 2007a Vol. III, and Capriles, under evaluation), I
believe totalizing metanarratives to be essential, though preliminary, aspects
of the spiritual therapy needed for healing the mind, society and the
ecosystem. However, in order to play this role, they must be structured in such
a way as to fulfill the dual purpose of serving as an antidote to the
assumptions of common sense—including the assumption that conceptual systems
can precisely match reality—and helping us develop the faith necessary to, (1)
set to apply the practices that lead beyond understanding in terms of thought,
into the immediate, direct, nonconceptual realization of the true condition of
ourselves and the whole of reality, and (2) set to work toward the
technological, economic, political, social (etc.) transformation indispensable
to resolve the ecological crisis we have produced (which as noted repeatedly
has put at stake the very continuity of human society and even of human
existence) and achieve what Tibetan Lama Chögyam Trungpa (1984) called “an
enlightened society.” This is why the value of such metanarratives depends on
their explicit acknowledgement that they are Aśvaghoṣian uses of
language arisen spontaneously from a perspective that does not confuse the maps
of words and concepts for the territory, which exhort us to get rid of the
delusory valuation of words and concepts and explain how can this be
achieved—as such being comparable to fingers pointing to the moon that we must
not confuse with the satellite, or to rafts for crossing to the other shore
(that of nirvāṇa) that must be left behind once we reach it.
Furthermore, in order to fulfill their aim, they must make it clear that the
task they indicate cannot be fulfilled by playing word games or by merely
achieving an intellectual understanding of reality, for it requires us to
wholeheartedly devote ourselves to a spiritual practice of the kind discussed
in this book—which cannot be learned in books or Internet courses, for it will
work only if we receive its transmission from a Teacher holding a true,
genuine, uninterrupted lineage originating in the source of the teachings, and
set to apply his or her instructions for going beyond the intellect.
A
major drawback of Derrida is that, as David Loy (1987) noted, he deconstructed
identity and the pairs of opposites, yet failed to deconstruct that which he
called différance and which in his view is the condition of possibility
of all differences—whereas Nāgārjuna, creator of Mādhyamaka
philosophy, as early as the beginning of the Christian era, by the same token
deconstructed the basis of identity and difference, thus leaving no ontological
assumption or basis for ontological assumptions unchallenged. In fact, as shown
elsewhere (Capriles, 2007a Vol. I), the highest systems of Buddhist philosophy—Mahāmādhyamaka,
and Mahāyāna and Vajrayāna Mādhyamaka Prāsaṅgika—and
the Dzogchen teachings are totally free from metaphysical assumptions and thus
need not undergo either deconstruction or reconstruction. As I see it, these
systems are by the same token antecedents, and keys to the production, of an
ontology free from the metaphysical assumptions of
phenomenology that would perfectly respond to the needs of our time. The latter
is what I set to elaborate in some of my works and that I refer to as metaphenomenology—which
can only be achieved by means of a method of
inquiry which, rather than basing its hermeneutics of experience exclusively on
the phenomena of saṃsāra, considers and privileges the
metaphenomenon/a of nirvāṇa [xiv]
that show all of the phenomena of saṃsāra and derived,
reified metaphysical assumptions to be baseless illusions.
The
metaphenomenology in question is also a metaontology: it is an ontology in that it discerns the nature of being
and of the entities which are in the process of being (essents), as well
as of nonbeing and so on. Whereas Western ontology so far has been based solely
on the experience founded on the phenomenon of being that is proper to saṃsāra,
what I refer to as metaontology is so called because, as noted above, it is principally based on the nirvanic unconcealment of
the true condition of ourselves and the whole of reality, in which the phenomenon
of being has dissolved and it has become evident that it was no more than a
baseless appearance pervading all experience conditioned by the basic human
delusion that, as the Mahāyāna
version of the Four Noble Truth makes it clear, constitutes the root of suffering—and
which, as I have explained in various works (Capriles, 1986, 1994, 2007a Vol.
III and minor works), is the root of ecological crisis as well. Therefore,
rather than taking being to be given or to constitute the true
nature of reality, it denounces it—together with the rest of the phenomena at
the root of the assumptions of metaphysics—as one of the most basic deceptive
appearances that issue from fully-fledged avidyā.
The
above-discussed metaontology is in stark contrast with the nihilistic façade
put on by many of the philosophical trends that, pretending to radically go
beyond the project and ideology of modernity, label themselves
postmodern—including those that purport to surpass ontology by circumscribing
themselves to the deconstruction of discourses. In fact, the root and essence
of modernity is the myth of evolutionary progress,
which, together with many of the metaphysical illusions and mistaken
assumptions proper to mainstream Western philosophy, continues to underlie a
great deal of so-called postmodern thought—including most works that, some
times on the basis of Heidegger-inspired hermeneutics, have attempted
“postmodern” reconstructions of the deconstructed. This is the case with Wilber
V, who claimed to have produced a post-metaphysical reconstruction of
primordial traditions that in his view can salvage the latter’s essence while
shedding their ontological baggage, yet continues to be under the spell of the
modern myth of progress and of a great deal of his former metaphysical assumptions
(a substantiation of this assertion is beyond the scope of this book, as it
would have to be so voluminous as to require a separate work).
Moreover,
the task the latest Wilber undertook could hardly be more pointless and futile,
for as show above, millennia ago the higher forms of Buddhist philosophy and
the highest Buddhist Path deconstructed whatever needed to be
deconstructed—unlike Derrida, including not only identity and difference, but
the condition of possibility of difference as well. If there remained anything
to do in our time, it would be to express the viewless viewpoint of the systems
of Buddhist philosophy and the Buddhist Path in question in an actualized,
reelaborated way, as a result of confronting them with the concepts and views of
Western philosophy from its onset until our time—which is precisely what I
attempted in many of my works (for an in-depth,
thorough exposition of my metaphenomenological, metaexistential
metaontology, cf. Capriles [2007a Vol. I]; for an in-depth discussion of
the blemishes of so-called postmodern philosophy and a thorough explanation of
what I view as genuinely post-modern, cf. Vol. III of the same work [Capriles,
2007a Vol. III] and a recent book in Spanish [Capriles, under evaluation]).
Finally,
in what regards spiritual traditions that are overly metaphysical in
nature—including Perennialism, which Wilber now rightly places in the premodern
category (which he established by contrast with the above-refuted, wrong use of
the term postmodern by a whole philosophical fauna)—Visser (op. cit.)
deems it extremely doubtful that the essence of the traditions in question will
come across in Wilber V’s version, which its author claims has been freed of
untenable teachings and categorizes as post-metaphysical. With regard to the
same traditions, Visser (op. cit.) says as well that Wilber’s latest
writings obliterate the difference between (exoteric) standard mythical
religious beliefs, and their (esoteric) mystical or so-called occult
reformulations, making the point that the reasons why modernity rejects most of
the premodern heritage must be carefully weighted—even though he views the
attempt to reframe perennialism into a form that is not offensive to either
modernity or postmodernity as an interesting exercise.
As
given to understand above, a thorough assessment of Wilber V would require an
altogether new work, as its intent is so ambitious—yet it would be currently
impossible to produce it because the new system by our author is in the process
of being built (one of the few works publicly published in what is presumably
its definitive form being Integral Spirituality [Wilber, 2007]). At the
time of writing this, the reader interested in exploring Wilber V may consult
Wilber (2001, 2002, 2003, 2007, 2010), Visser (undated),
Kazlev (undated) and Reynolds’ (undated) eulogy of Wilber.